This is a Q & A blog post by our Visiting Scholar in Philosophy, William Lane Craig.
Question
Big fan of your work Dr. Craig. My question is about what specifically ties the soul to the physical mind of a person. You鈥檝e spoken in the past about how to be human is to be a body/soul composite, the spirit and the physical mechanisms of the universe working in tandem. The spirit or mind makes a willful decision, which acts upon the physical brain and performs physical actions in our reality.
What would you say ties the spirit or mind specifically to a single body or brain? Why can any human mind only act upon the physical body it鈥檚 been 鈥渁ssigned鈥 to, for lack of a better term, and not some other collection of matter and particles?
Thank you, and God bless.
Jacob
United States
William Lane Craig鈥檚 Response
The problem you raise here, Jacob, is known in the philosophical literature as 鈥渢he causal pairing problem.鈥 As explained by Jaegwon Kim, the problem is how to explain the causal connection between a particular cause and a particular effect. In the case of physical substances, a causal connection between two events exists in virtue of their spatial relations, such as their spatial orientation and the path along which a causal chain between them lies. But assuming that the soul, being immaterial, is not spatially located, the causal connection between mental events and physical events is said to be inexplicable.
To illustrate the problem, we鈥檙e invited to imagine two souls, A and B, who are in the same mental state, for example, willing to lift the left arm of one鈥檚 body. If souls are not spatially located in their respective bodies, then there seems to be no explanation why A鈥檚 willing causes A鈥檚 arm to rise rather than B鈥檚 arm. One cannot say that the explanation lies in the fact that the body in question is A鈥檚 body, for the reason it is A鈥檚 body is because of A鈥檚 causal connection to it, so that such an explanation would be viciously circular. Dualism thus seems unable to explain the pairing of mental causes with their physical effects.
Kim鈥檚 causal pairing problem involves two claims: (1) causation requires pairing relations connecting a cause to its effect and (2) there are no such relations for minds because they are not spatially located. Both of these claims may be challenged.
With regard to (2), dualists who hold that souls do exist spatially in or throughout their bodies will be unfazed by Kim鈥檚 objection, since souls meet successfully the condition for being causally connected to their effects. The objection does remain relevant for dualist-interactionists who think that souls do not have spatial locations. But then the question becomes why we should think that only spatial relations can pair a cause with its effect. Prima facie this seems overly restrictive.
As for (1) the claim assumes that there must be some pairing relation that connects causes and their effects. Why think this? Kim does not say. Bailey, Rasmussen and Van Horn speculate, 鈥淲e have a guess as to the underlining [sic] reasoning for thinking that there must be a pairing relation: pairing is required because the satisfaction of a generality condition is necessary for causation,鈥 for example,
"(GC) Necessarily, if A and B share all of their qualitative properties, then A is no more qualified to count as the cause of C than B is."
Now Kim presupposes the truth of event causation, the view that causal relations hold only between events. But many dualist-interactionists embrace agent causation, the view that agents bring about effects by means of their actions. Bailey et al. contend that libertarian causal agency constitutes an exception to any generality condition like (GC) stipulating that qualitatively indistinguishable causes (like souls) cannot have different effects:
"It鈥檚 common for immaterialists about human persons to think that a person can enjoy agent causal powers that allow her to choose an action among a range of alternative actions. The idea is that no property instantiated prior to the time of the agent鈥檚 action fixes exactly which action she performs. . . . We think such immaterialists would happily grant in addition that indistinguishable agents would (or at least could) have the same causal capacities. Now consider a world in which two persons, Tim and Tom, are exactly similar in all respects. . . . Suppose that Tim and Tom each have the same two options available to them鈥攖o cause A or to refrain from causing A. If Tom happens to cause A while Tim refrains, then we have a situation in which GC fails. The reason is that Tom and Tim are indistinguishable and yet Tom counts as the cause of A, whereas Tim does not."
If libertarian free agents are causes of effects, then a soul could be the cause of a particular physical effect even though nothing distinguishes it qualitatively from another soul. Gregory Ganssle concludes that 鈥淜im鈥檚 argument will work only against those versions of dualism that do not include an agent-causation view. Any position that involves this kind of agency will be immune from Kim鈥檚 argument.鈥
Intriguingly, since Kim鈥檚 argument is meant to hold for immaterial mental substances in general, there should be a theological version of it, which has been called the divine causal pairing problem. The challenge here is to explain, given God鈥檚 transcendence of space, why His mental events are causally connected with certain events in the physical world rather than others.
Fortunately, it鈥檚 difficult even to state the pairing problem for God鈥檚 causal activity in a way that does not appear a bit silly. For example, Ganssle writes, 鈥淚f we need some relation to be present to link cause and effect, we will need a link between God鈥檚 willing and its effect. God wills that the Red Sea part. What makes it the case that this results in the parting of the Red Sea rather than the Mediterranean Sea?鈥 It is bewildering how such a question can even be posed with respect to an omnipotent being Whose volitions are inevitably fulfilled. The will of such a being is indefectible鈥攏ecessarily, it is linked to its effect. It is metaphysically impossible that God wills the parting of the Red Sea and the Mediterranean parts instead. So, while for some physical causes such as a rock鈥檚 hitting and breaking a window, 鈥渢he spatiotemporal relation is sufficient to map the cause to a particular effect,鈥 says Ganssle, 鈥淚t is possible that, when God acts, it is the direct object of his volition that maps the cause to the intended effect.鈥 Indeed, necessarily, whatever God wills shall be done, on Earth as it is in heaven.
Notes
Jaegwon Kim, Physicalism, or Something Near Enough (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005), pp. 78鈥88.
As Andrew M. Bailey, Joshua Rasmussen, and Luke Van Horn, 鈥淣o pairing problem,鈥 Philosophical Studies 154 (2011): 349-60, point out, Kim鈥檚 claim entails that the initial cosmological singularity featured in the standard Big Bang model could not possibly have been caused, given that the singularity is thought to represent the beginning of the existence of space.
Plantinga protests, 鈥淚s it really clear that in any case of causation, there must be this factor X that pairs up event A with event B, that makes it the case that A is the cause of B? . . . why must we suppose that there is such a factor X? Consider the similar and oft-asked question about identity over time. What is it that makes it the case that object A at time t is identical with object B at some earlier time t*? . . . Many answers have been proposed, but none seems to work. And perhaps the right answer to the question is: there isn鈥檛 anything (anything else, so to speak) that makes it the case that A is identical with B. Identity doesn鈥檛 have to supervene on other properties. Couldn鈥檛 it be the same in the case of causation?鈥 (Alvin Plantinga, 鈥淢aterialism and Christian Belief,鈥 in Persons: Human and Divine, ed. Peter van Inwagen and Dean Zimmerman [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007], p. 132).
Bailey, Rasmussen, and Van Horn, 鈥淣o pairing problem,鈥 p. 354.
Gregory E. Ganssle, 鈥淒ivine Causation and the Pairing Problem,鈥 in Divine Causation, ed. Gregory E. Ganssle (London: Routledge, 2022), p. 272.
Ganssle, 鈥淒ivine Causation and the Pairing Problem,鈥 p. 269. Bailey, Rasmussen, and Van Horn, 鈥淣o pairing problem,鈥 p. 351, earlier noted this consequence of Kim鈥檚 objection.
Ganssle, 鈥淒ivine Causation and the Pairing Problem,鈥 p. 274.
As Mullins and Byrd remind us, 鈥淐lassical Christian theology is . . . committed to God鈥檚 infallible causal power. God鈥檚 causal power is infallible in that, if God wills or causes some state of affairs x, then it is not possible for x to fail to obtain. This is sometimes captured by saying that if God intentionally acts to bring about some state of affairs, then that state of affairs is hypothetically necessary鈥 (R.T. Mullins and Shannon Eugene Byrd, 鈥淒ivine Simplicity and Modal Collapse: A Persistent Problem,鈥 European Journal for Philosophy of Religion [forthcoming]). So, in answer to the question, 鈥淲hat is that factor X in the case of alleged divine causation?鈥 Plantinga answers, 鈥渉ere there appears to be an easy answer. According to classical theism, it鈥檚 a necessary truth that whatever God wills, takes place. . . . So what is it that makes it the case that God鈥檚 intentions cause what they cause? To ask that question is like asking, 鈥榃hat is it that makes an equiangular triangle equilateral?鈥 The answer is (broadly) logical necessity; it鈥檚 necessary that whatever God wills comes to be, just as it鈥檚 necessary that every equiangular triangle be equilateral鈥 (Plantinga, 鈥淢aterialism and Christian Belief,鈥 p. 133).
Ganssle, 鈥淒ivine Causation and the Pairing Problem,鈥 p. 276.